Uit: Language in Thought and Action, door S.I. Hayakawa.
Chapter 10
Why We Must Abstract
This process of abstracting, of leaving characteristics out, is an indispensable
convenience. To illustrate by still another example, suppose that we live in an
isolated village of four families, each owning a house. A's house is referred to
as maga, B's house is biyo; C's is kata, and D's is
pelel. This is quite satisfactory for ordinary purposes of communication in
the village, unless a discussion arises about building a new house-a spare one,
let us say. We cannot refer to the projected house by any one of the four words
we have for the existing houses, since each of these has too specific a meaning.
We must find a general term, at a higher level of abstraction, that means
"something that has certain characteristics in common with maga, biyo,
kata, and pelel, and yet is not A's, B's, C's, or D's." Since this
is much too complicated to say each time, an abbreviation must be
invented. So we choose the noise, house. Out of such needs do our words
come-they are a form of shorthand. The invention of a new abstraction is a great
step forward, since it makes discussion possible - as, in this case, not
only the discussion of a fifth house, but of all future houses we may build or
see in our travels or dream about.
A producer of educational films once remarked to the writer
that it is impossible to make a shot of "work." You can shoot Joe hoeing
potatoes, Frank greasing a car, Bill spraying paint on a barn, but never just
"work." "Work," too, is a shorthand term, standing, at a higher level of
abstraction, for a characteristic that a multitude of activities, from
dishwashing to navigation to running an advertising agency to governing a
nation, have in common. The special meaning that "work" has in physics is also
clearly derived from abstracting the common characteristics of many different
kinds of work. ("A transference of energy from one body to another, resulting in
the motion or displacement of the body acted upon, in the direction of the
acting force and against resistance." Funk and Wagnalls' Standard College
Dictionary.) The indispensability of this process of abstracting can again
be illustrated by what we do when we "calculate." The word "calculate"
originates from the Latin word calculus, meaning "pebble," and derives
its present meaning from such ancient practices as putting a pebble into a box
for each sheep as it left the fold, so that one could tell, by checking the
sheep returning at night against the pebbles, whether any had been lost.
Primitive as this example of calculation is, it will serve to show why
mathematics works. Each pebble is, in this example, an abstraction representing
the "oneness" of each sheep - its numerical value. And because we are
abstracting from extensional events on clearly understood and uniform
principles, the numerical facts about the pebbles are also, barring unforeseen
circumstances, numerical facts about the sheep. Our x's and y's and other
mathematical symbols are abstractions made from numerical abstractions, and are
therefore abstractions of still higher level. And they are useful in predicting
occurrences and in getting work done because, since they are abstractions
properly and uniformly made from starting points in the extensional world, the
relations revealed by the symbols will be, again barring unforeseen
circumstances, relations existing in the extensional world.
Naar Hayakawa, contents
, Algemene semantiek lijst
, Algemene semantiek overzicht
, of site home
.
|