Uit: Language in Thought and Action, door S.I. Hayakawa.
Chapter 10
Operational Definitions
Another way to keep extensional levels in mind, when definitions are called for,
is to use what physicist P. W. Bridgman called "operational definitions." As he
says,
|
To find the length of an object, we have to perform certain physical
operations. The concept of length is therefore fixed when the operations
by which length is measured are fixed. ... In general, we mean by any
concept nothing more than a set of operations; the concept is
synonymous with the corresponding set of operations.1 |
The operational definition, then, as Anatol Rapoport
explains, is one that tells you "what to do and what to observe in
order to bring the thing defined or its effects within the range of one's
experience." He gives the following simple example of how to define "weight": go
to a railroad station or drugstore, look for a scale, stand on it, put in a
penny, read the number at which the pointer comes to rest. That is your
weight. But supposing different scales give different readings? Then your weight
can be said to be within the range of, say, 140 to 145 pounds. With more
accurate scales you might get closer readings, such as 142 pounds plus-or-minus
one. But there is no "property" called weight that exists apart from the
operations measuring it. As Rapoport says, "If the only way we can be aware of
the amount of weight is by means of the scale, then the very definition of
weight has to be in terms of the scale." 3
Such, then, is the scientific, or "operational," point of
view towards definition---one that attempts rigidly to exclude non-extensional,
non-sense statements. We can extend this idea from science to the problems of
everyday life and thought. Just as there is no such thing as "length" apart from
the operations by which length is measured, just as there is no "weight" apart
from the operations by which weight is determined, there is likewise no
"democracy" apart from the sum-total of democratic practices, such as
universal franchise, freedom of speech, equality before the law, and so on.
Similarly, there is no such thing as "brotherhood" apart from brotherly
behavior, nor "charity" apart from charitable actions.
The operational point of view does much to keep our words
meaningful. When people say things like, "Let's have no more of progressive
methods in our schools," "Let's get back to sound business principles in
running our county government," "Let's try to do the Christian thing,"
"Let's put father back as head of the family," we are entitled to ask, "what do
you mean - extensionally speaking? To ask this question often - of
ourselves as well as of others-is to do our bit towards reducing the vast amount
of non-sense that is written, spoken, and shouted in this incredibly garrulous
world.
The best examples in everyday life of operational definitions
are to be found in cookbooks, which describe the operations by means of
which the entity defined may be extensionally experienced. Thus: "Steak Diane.
Slice tenderloin beef very thin and give it a few whacks with a meat mallet to
flatten it even more; sprinkle with salt and pepper to taste. Have your pan very
hot. . . ." (The Sunset Cook Book.) Writers and speakers would do well to
study cookbooks occasionally to increase the clarity and verifiability of their
utterances.
1 The Logic of Modern Physics
(1927), p. 5.
Naar Hayakawa, contents
, Algemene semantiek lijst
, Algemene semantiek overzicht
, of site home
.
|